An essay I wrote a few years ago but never posted. My first encounter with Nietzsche--feel the excitement:
Perhaps the greatest source of Nietzsche’s authority is best stated by himself:
Perhaps the greatest source of Nietzsche’s authority is best stated by himself:
Posthumous
human beings—like me, for example—are understood worse than
timely ones, but they are listened
to better.
More accurately: we are never understood—and that’s
the
source of our authority… (Nietzsche 7)
This
epigram seems to demonstrate that Nietzsche had at least some inkling
of the power he held over his readers. Today, Nietzsche is one of the
most divisive, well known, and incontrovertibly misunderstood
contributors to the modern philosophical tradition. The most central
obstacle in attempting to come to certain conclusions about Nietzsche
is that Nietzsche asks more questions than he provides answers. It is
extremely tempting to label Nietzsche: misogynist, nihilist,
rational, irrational, atheist, hedonist etc. One could probably make
a case for any of these labels. To label Nietzsche, is to misread
Nietzsche. To confine him to a label is to assume a logical
consistency. “A foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little
minds”, as Emerson (one of Nietzsche’s more admired authors)
would have it. This confinement underestimates the complexity of
Nietzsche, as a reading is more like a study in contradictions.
Considering Nietzsche rejected rational thought in general, logical
conclusions are antithetical to the whole of his philosophy. This is
not to say his ideas are in chaos, only that Nietzsche is
anti-systematic. (Lecture 4/14) It is clear that Nietzsche is large
and does contain multitudes. While Nietzsche rejects many ideals of
the 17th
century Enlightenment, much of his philosophy stems from an
Enlightenment tradition. He is an anti-Enlightenment thinker, and in
many ways, an Enlightenment thinker.
Descartes, the father of Enlightenment thinking, is an especial target of criticism for Nietzsche. Descartes sees sensory perception as a deception. In his Discourse on Method, Descartes plainly states, “…our senses sometimes deceive us, I wanted to suppose that nothing was exactly as they led us to imagine.” (Descartes 18) So here Descartes tells us to doubt all external perceptions because he strongly believes in internal rational analysis. In other words, think before you act. Nietzsche turns this entire philosophy on its head in Twilight of the Idols. Nietzsche explicitly writes, “’Reason’ is what causes us to falsify the testimony of the senses…they do not lie”. (Nietzsche 19) Here lies the fundamental difference between Nietzsche and Descartes. To Nietzsche, living is feeling; specifically, acting off of the urges and instincts which may be retrained or denied by reason. Descartes’ very definition of the self heavily conflicts with Nietzsche.
Descartes describes the idea of an intrinsic separation between mind and body, known as Cartesian Dualism. The idea itself, places identity within the mind, with much less value associated with the body. Descartes explains,
Thus
this “I”, that is to say, the soul through which I am what I am,
is entirely distinct from the body and is even easier to know than
the body, and even if there were no body at all, it would not cease
to be all that it is. (Descartes 19)
As
we can see, Descartes regards the body as theoretically superfluous
to one’s existence, or at least to the experience of existence. The
rejection of rational identity is central to Nietzsche’s
philosophy. Nietzsche equates such rationality to an Apollonian
state. The Greek figure of Apollo represents truth, order, reason,
perfection, system etc. Essentially, Apollo is a representation of
all that is weak and effeminate in the eyes of Nietzsche. Moreover,
Nietzsche certainly held Dionysian qualities in the highest regard.
Near the end of Twilight,
Nietzsche
posits:
Saying
yes to life even in its most strange and intractable problems, the
will to life, celebrating its own inexhaustibility by sacrificing
its highest types—that
is what I call Dionysian, (Nietzsche 91)
Here
we find one of Nietzsche’s most prominent passions, the will of
life. To truly live, Nietzsche finds, we cannot be bogged down by
heavy systematic reasoning. He wishes to live by instinct and writes,
“Everything good
is instinct—and consequently is easy”. (Nietzsche 31)
The Enlightenment was a period when science and revelation could finally begin to separate. Reason and not scripture would now pave the way to truth. Any casual reader of Nietzsche can conclude that he rejects religion as a whole. One would then think that Nietzsche might embrace much of this Enlightenment thinking. Indeed, in many ways he does. While the Enlightenment did take the first step in transferring academia into a more secular form of learning, the reality is that the 17th century was not yet ready to completely cast off religion. Instead, religion was accommodated and reconciled with science. And this accommodation is the receiver of Nietzsche’s wrath. Deism, in particular, sought to secularize the moral tradition of Christianity. Because of their identity with Christian morality, Nietzsche finds the Enlightenment thinkers just as reprehensible as the Christians he so prominently despises:
They’ve
gotten rid of the Christian God, and now they think they have to hold
onto Christian morality all the more: that’s English
logic…if you give up Christian faith, you pull the right
to Christian morality out from under your feet. (Nietzsche 53)
This
“English
logic”
likely refers to John Stuart Mill, an English contemporary of
Nietzsche, who was a proponent of 19th
century Rationalism. Nietzsche views Mill as a backwards thinker who
lives in 17th
century ideology. Mill, while dismissing Christianity in general,
states his belief in the validity of a Christian moral code:
I
believe that other ethics than any which can be evolved from
exclusively Christian sources must exist side by side with Christian
ethics to produce the moral regeneration of mankind…it is not
necessary that in ceasing to ignore the moral truths not contained in
Christianity men should ignore any of those which it does contain.
(Mill 49)
This
is a sort of cafeteria style philosophy which Nietzsche criticizes
Mill for. It’s odd because Nietzsche seems to think you either can
take Christianity and therefore you are a mindless sheep, or you take
none of it and are thus better off for that decision. This is a
rather black and white view, one which is not consistent with the
whole of Nietzsche’s philosophy. In fact, Mill’s utilization of
Christian morality along with his dismissal of the Christian faith
echoes exactly what Nietzsche does with Enlightenment rationalism.
While Nietzsche rejects the Enlightenment in general, he utilizes its
more rational reasoning in his rejection of mysticism and theocracy.
Thus perhaps, here Nietzsche cannot justify himself in his criticism
of Mill’s methods. Of course, as stated above, Nietzsche should
never be taken as a rationally consistent critic.
If there is one label Nietzsche has never been confined to, it is that he has never been accused of being unoriginal. Whether he is criticizing the Enlightenment, or utilizing it (or both) one can be sure that what he is saying has never quite been stated the same way before. He is provocative and one is forced to confront every belief one has even taken for granted while reading him. Our offenses are our “Idols”; idols which Nietzsche believes should be reevaluated. Above all, to rely on our instincts, and reject conformity (especially as displayed in organized religion) perhaps then one can truly live. “Trust thyself: every heart vibrates to that iron string.”1
Works
Cited
Descartes,
René. Discourse
on the method for conducting one's reason well and for seeking truth
in the sciences.
Hackett Pub Co Inc, 1998.
Mill,
John Stuart. On
liberty.
Hackett Publishing, 1978.
Nietzsche,
Friedrich. Twilight
of the idols, or, How to philosophize with the hammer.
Hackett Publishing, 1997.
1
Emerson, Self-Reliance
No comments:
Post a Comment